p. 361 Buddhism not only offers a system of ethics, it is fundamentally concerned with human conduct in the most ample meaning of the word. Buddhism did face the basic problems of moral axiology, both in its early and late speculations, although its method and vocabulary are different from that of the Western philosopher. Moreover, it is in this fact that we find one of the distinctive characteristics of Buddhism among the Indian systems of salvation. Specially in contrast to the Vedaantins, with whom the Buddhists share many common traits in the order of metaphysics, Buddhism places value above being, existence above essence, function above structure. It is in the realm of ethics that we find Buddhism's great contribution to Indian thought. The Four Noble Truths, for instance, formulated in clear opposition to the amoralistic speculations of the age, do not represent a mere statement of dogma or metaphysics, rather, they constitute one of the first expressions of ethical theory in the history of philosophy. Yet, in spite of the evident fact that Buddhism taught a positive moral and ethical doctrine, the accusation of nihilism has been cast against Buddhism ever since its beginnings. More than once Gautama had to reaffirm his position of a middle way between nihilism and realism, moral and metaphysical.(1) In fact, avoiding these two extremes was the main philosophical problem of Buddhism. The question was always "how can we deny `own-existence' (svabhaava)(2) without falling into nihilism." Perhaps the latter schools were more often led by dogmatical considerations than by any sincere interest in safeguarding ethical values; the main issue was, then, not how to insure salvation, but rather how to secure orthodoxy. Nevertheless, the problem of the metaphysical justification of the path would always ------------------------------ Professor Luis O. Gomez is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Puerto Rico. AUTHOR'S NOTE: The substance of this article was delivered before the faculty and students of the Department of Indian Philosophy and Buddhist Studies of the University of Kyoto in October, 1968. All unmarked references in the text are to the Bodhicaryaavataara of `Santideva, chapter and stanza (roman and arabic numerals), as numbered in Poussin's ed., Calcutta, 1902-1914. Abbreviations used in the notes: Ako`s., Abhidharmako`sa of Vasubandhu, ed. P. Pradhan, (Patna, 1967) (chapter and stanza); Bcaa., Bodhicaryaavataara of `Saantideva (see above); MK., Madhyamakakaarikaa of Naagaarjuna, ed. L. de la Yallee Poussin (St. Petersburg: Impr. de l'Academie imperiale des sciences, 1912) (chapter and stanza); Rat., Ratnaavalii of Naagaarjuna, ed. Guiseppe Tucci, Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society (JRAS) (London, 1934 and 1936) (chapter and stanza) ; Siks., `Sik.saasamuccaya of Saantideva, ed. Cecil Bendall (St.Petersburg, 1902) (quoted by page number). 1. Cf., for example, A^nguttara-Nikaaya IV.174, 180, 182 ff. 2. svabhaavaa, "own-becoming" or ("self-existence," the term's extension includes the supposed referents of our terms substance, essence, nature, character. I have translated it literally rather than using an inappropriate equivalent. For a discussion of this term and ample references, see Jacques May, Prasannapadaa Madhyamakavrtti: douze chapitres. (Paris: Adrien-Maissonneuve, 1959), p. 324, note 328. For the Aristotelian concept of ousia (ovoia) , which is probably closer to suabhaava than the medieval substance, cf. Metaphysics, V.8, VII.1-6, 16-17. p. 362 remain the avowed purpose of all philosophical speculation; thus, beyond the complicated question of orthodoxy, and at a more immediate and fundamental level, would lie the problem of ethics and salvation. Although ethics is often identified with morality, it would not be pertinent to the purpose of this article to clarify the doctrine of morality (`siila), that is, particular problems regarding rules of conduct. The issue is the foundation for the necessity of ethics, or, rather, of human perfection (paaramitaa). The problem may be stated summarily as follows: how can perfection be necessary, or at all possible, without a substance and essence of the human subject (aatman)? There seems to be a radical contradiction between the doctrine of nonself, or, even more, that of emptiness, and any possible moral obligation.(3) In the face of this paradox, the Buddhist attitude has not been always as innocently sanguine as the words of `Saantideva would seem: "All dharmas are without self, yet this does not contradict the connection of the fruit with the act."(4) The question has been seriously debated more than once in the history of Buddhism; by `Saantideva himself and, earlier in the Maadhyamika tradition, in the locus classicus which is chapter XXIV of the Maahyamaka`saastra. Naagaarjuna's argumentation, however, constitutes a refutation of ethical absolutism, not a defense of the Buddhist position in ethics. This position is that precisely from the fact of selflessness man is convinced of the necessity of good conduct. This stand is illustrated rather dramatically in such texts as the Saundaraananda, or, for that matter, many a modern manual of Buddhist morality. These texts perhaps justify morality only in the narrowest sense: the detachment which they promulgate evokes the image of a solitary monk, indifferent to the world suffering around him. At the very least, the emphasis is on a morality of continence (sa^mvara`siila) rather than a positive system of value (sattvaarthakriyaa`siila). The Mahaayaana claims that it offers such a system and that it is possible only on the basis of the doctrine of nonself and universal emptiness. The argument runs that nonself necessarily leads to detachment and renunciation, which then lead to altruism in its highest forms. The `Sik.saasamuccaya, for instance, affirms that once the emptiness of personality (pudgala) is established, all defilements are uprooted, and they never grow again.(5) Once the ------------------------------------ 3. The paradox involved in the simultaneous assertion of nairaatmya and karmaphala was first pointed out in the West by Hendrik Kern in his Manual of Indian Buddhism (1896) (Varanasi: Indological Book House, 1968), pp. 49-50, the problem has been discussed in detail by Louis de la Vallee Poussin in his papers "La negation de 1'ame et la doctrine de l'acte" (JA, Sept.-Oct., no. 20 (1902): 237-306) and "Nouvelles recherches sur la doctrine de l'acte" (JA, Nov.-Dec., no. 2 (1903): pp. 357-450). 4. `Sik.s. 244, referring to the Pit.rputrasamaagama: "All dharmas are without a self, yet this does not exclude the connection of the fruit to the act. Moreover, because they have no self-existence, there is no contradiction with the fact that all dharmas are as they are seen" 5. `Sik.s. 242. p. 363 very notion of self is removed, all attachment to self disappears, then there will be no more attachment to profit.(6) What is more, good conduct is not only necessary for the attainment of selflessness, but once selflessness is attained, good conduct follows spontaneously.(7) For, `Saantideva claims, "only from abandonment comes success in the attainment of one's own goals."(8) Moreover, compassion is considered to be the very foundation of the path to enlightenment, and it is also its culmination.(9) As enunciated by `Saantideva in the Bodhicaryaavataara: "...deliverance (nirvaa.na) is complete renunciation, and I seek deliverance; if I must renounce everything, it would be better to give [everything] to [other] living beings" (III.11). Implicit in this stanza is the principle that renunciation or, even better, the true selflessness of complete renunciation (in nirvaa.na), finds its fulfillment in altruism. This principle is enunciated implicitly: Giving and the other perfections are more perfect in the order [in which they are stated. The bodhisattva] would not give up one better for another [less good], except in the case of [compassionate generosity, which is] the dam [that retains the waters of merit] of the [bodhisattva's] career. Understanding this [principle, the bodhisattva] applies himself constantly to the welfare of others; compassionate, he should even consent [to carry out] a sinful act if he perceives that it could be for the well-being [of others] (V.83-84).(10) In other words, although in the order of pure excellence the highest perfection is wisdom, (because, so to speak, it illuminates the others), still, in the practical order, compassion takes precedence, because it is the dam that holds the bodhisattva's career. In what sense? The reader will look for an answer in vain. The Pa~njikaa is equally silent. Perhaps the answer to this question should be sought elsewhere, in the eighth chapter. The eighth chapter of the Bodhicaryaavataara, dedicated to dhyaana, was no doubt written with the sole purpose of presenting `Saantideva's ------------------------------- 6. `Sik.s. 11, quoting the Pramuditaabhuumi of Da`sabhuumika, found on p. 17 of Ryuuko Kondo's ed.; p. 13 of J. Rahder's ed. 7. `Sik.s. 121. In this connection, the interdependence of morality and wisdom is another form of expressing the same idea, for which see Diigha Nikaaya I.124. It is also important to point to the difference in the Mahaayaana and the Theravaala view of compassion. The latter conceives of it as a mere preliminary, whereas the Mahaayaana accepts it as a necessary counterpart of wisdom. For the Theravaadin position, see: Abhidhammatthasa^ngaha, Part II.I1 and Part IX, Ako`s. VII.33, also Herbert V. Guenther, Philosophy and Psychology in the Abhidharma, (Lucknow: Buddha Vihara, 1957), pp. 161-165, and 301, note 3. On the interdependence of the paaramitaa, see `Satasaahasrikaa, chap.X (pp.1466-1469 in P. Ghosha's ed., Calcutta, 1902-1913) and A.s.tasaahasrikaa, chaps. III and XXV (pp. 80-81 and 431 of Mitra's ed., Calcutta, 1888). 8. `Sik.s. 145. 9. The basis of the bodhicitta is compassion: `Sik.s. 7-8. Compare also `Sik.s. 11, Bcaa. V.42, and Bodhisattvabhuumi, N. Dutt's ed. (Patna, 1967), pp. 97-126; Unrai Wogihara's ed. (Tokyo: 1930), pp. 140-182. 10. See references to Bodhisattvabhuumi in note 9 herein. p. 364 own Mahaayaanist concept of meditation. According to the author, the prime object of meditation is, of course, inner calm (`samatha) (VIII.4); but this calm is only preparatory to the real object of meditation: namely, the thought of enlightenment (bodhicitta) (VIII.89). The bodhicitta, or germinal thought of awakening, is developed through two meditational practices, according to this chapter; the paraatmasamataa and the paraatmaparivartana. Paraatmasamataa, or the basic equality between self and others, is best described in the words of `Saantideva: First he should develop earnestly the notion of nondifference of self and others [in the following way: ] all beings have sorrow and happiness as I do, they should therefore be protected by me as if they were my own self. As the body should be protected as one, although it has many parts, so should one protect everything in the world with its many divisions, for it is one in sorrow and happiness. Although my suffering is not felt in other bodies, yet it is difficult to bear because of my love of self; likewise, though I myself cannot experience the sorrow of others, this sorrow is difficult to bear for others because of their love of self. The sorrow of others I must destroy, because it is sorrow as much as my own, and I must help others because they are living beings as much as myself. When we consider that happiness is equally pleasant to me and to others, then what special quality do I have which could justify striving [only] after my own good? When we consider that fear and sorrow are unpleasant to me and to others, then what special quality do I have by which I should protect myself, not another (VIII.90-96). He who wants to protect himself as well as others should practice the supreme mystery: "Behave towards yourself as the worldly do towards others, and towards others, do as they do towards themselves." (VIII.120).(11) Paraatmaparivartana, or the substitution of self for others, follows as a corollary to this last statement. It is described by `Saantideva as the giving of one's ego to another and the adoption of that person's ego as one's own. What is specially significant is the reason `Saantideva gives for the practice of this substitution: because the notion of a self and the attachment which originates in it are the only causes of all suffering in this world, one should give up such a notion (VIII.134). Altruism is an exercise in renunciation. Thus, if I give my "I" to another, and adopt his "I," it is both to appease my suffering and the suffering of others (VIII.136). At this point we are ready to understand why `Saantideva had said earlier that altruism should take precedence over the development of any of the "private virtues." Altruism acts as the safeguard, the dam, of all other virtues, of all moral perfection, because it is the only guarantee of active selflessness. `Saantideva considers compassion as the most effective antidote against the surreptitious selfishness of solitary asceticism. Still, we are in doubt: Why altruism? Because, there being no self, replies -------------------------------- 11. Although rhetorically this is the converse of the Christian dictum "You shall love your neighbor as yourself" (Matt. 19: 19) , the purport is identical. p. 365 the Buddhist, there is no reason why we should avoid our sorrow and not that of others. "If [you contend that this avoidance of only our own suffering], although unreasonable, is a fact arising from our notion of a self, [we answer that] if it is not reasonable, then it should be rejected by all means, both in respect to the self and in respect to others" (VIII.100). As the following stanza explains: "A series (sa^mtaana) or an aggregate (samudaya) are as false as a line [of ants] or an army: there is no one to whom sorrow could belong; therefore, [who could claim] that [certain sorrows] are his own? All sorrows without exception have no owner, only because they are sorrow should they be avoided, no special rule is applicable in respect to this" (VIII.101-102). At this point the following objection is presented: "If there is no subject who suffers here in sa^msaara, then there is no reason why we should avoid sorrow (our own or that of others), since there exists no suffering being who could be the recipient of compassion." Although this objection has been implicitly answered in the previous stanzas, `Saantideva replies: "Then, why should we avoid pain? Because everybody agrees on that. If it is to be avoided, then all [should be] equally [avoided]. If not to be avoided, then the self too [should be treated] as [other] beings" (VIII.103). At this point the Pa~njikaa comments, with a slight tinge of irony: It is not reasonable to argue that sorrow should not be avoided because there is no self. Why? Because [the avoidance of sorrow is accepted] by everyone without objection or contention. Even the Caarvaakas avoid their own suffering. Yet, they are certainly not free from error, because they accept a self and since the essence of a self cannot be apprehended. Moreover, its existence is not proven by mere acceptance, and there is no means of valid cognition that can prove it, while there are many things which contradict it. Consequently, if we must avoid sorrow, then we must avoid all sorrows, and if we will not avoid them all, then we should not avoid our own either. [That is to say, if you could validate your claim,] our conclusion [would then be] that our own sorrow, which is of the nature of the five groups of grasping, should not be avoided as [in the case of] all [other] beings, since there is no true difference [between the self and others] (Pa~njikaa ad VIII.103). Of course, a real objector would not be satisfied by such an answer. It seems that the argument is on two different levels. On the one hand, what is conventionally true is rejected, on the other hand, the author appeals to the belief of common man in support of his thesis. What are the author's criteria for accepting or rejecting the validity of common knowledge? How can he defend his position if he will say that sorrow itself is only the result of illusion and that upon destroying the notion of self all sorrows disappear? (at VIII. 134-135). It is evident that `Saantideva himself was not wholly satisfied with the explanation we have quoted, for he felt it necessary to take up the issue again at IX.76-78: "If there are no beings, for whom shall we feel compassion?" "[We feel p. 366 compassion for a being] who has been imagined through an illusion accepted [as real] for the sake of the goal to be attained" (IX.76). Praj~naakaramati comments: ... For it is Buddhahood that we seek... and Buddhahood cannot be attained while there is perception of any dharmas; and the nonperception of all dharmas is achieved through development of wisdom; and this development of wisdom occurs through constant exercise for a long period of time. But this effort is produced under the surveillance of compassion, compassion is first exercised toward suffering living beings, and constitutes the basis for the obtainment of the rest of the equipment. Therefore, one should accept the illusion of existing living beings for the sake of the object to be attained.... Therefore, there is first compassion with beings for its object, secondly, with dharmas for its object, and lastly with no object at all.(12) Thus, although through wisdom the nonobjectivity of beings is described from the point of view of the ultimate goal (paramaarthata.h), in terms of covering truth (sa^mv.rtyaa), they are not contradicted. This has been explained in the following stanza: "Because wisdom shares in reality, and compassion in covering, after considering things as they are, it occurred to you: `There are no beings in this world. But, when you became full of compassion, the mother of the ten forces, then your love for the suffering world was like that of a father to his son."(13) In the Catu.hstava too, it is said: "Nowhere, Protector, do you hold the conception of a being, yet you are above all compassionate to suffering living beings"(l4) (Pa~njikaa ad IX.76 c-d). Apparently, `Saantideva and Praj~naakaramati have resorted to dogmatics at this point. They seem to be trying to save the Buddhist path at all cost, in spite of the fact that their philosophy seems to contradict the path and all its implications. Surprisingly, the objector is relentless and attacks the very notion of the path: "'If there are no beings, then whose is the task to be performed?' `Effort too is truly the result of illusion. But, an illusion which leads to the goal, and the purpose of which is to allay the suffering of living beings, should not be rejected' " (IX.77). The objector replies in the Pa~njikaa: "'But, then why not accept the idea of a self?' " (ad IX.77). `Saantideva explains: "From the illusion of a self... egotism, which is the cause of all suffering, increases. If egotism cannot be destroyed from this view of a self, then it is better to cultivate the idea of nonself" (IX.78). This passage, a veritable justification of error, will not be as puzzling as it seems if we turn back to `Saantideva's justification of emptiness (`suunyataa) in IX.47-53. What is the value of emptiness? The author of the `Sik.saasamuccaya explains that emptiness is superior to other-views (like that of mere nonself: anaatmataa) in that it destroys all attachment, all grasping, including that which is the obstacle of conception (j~neyaavara.na), whereas other doctrines can only destroy passionate attachment (kli.s.t.at.r.snaa) (IX.47). ----------------------------- 12. `Sik.s. 212, according to the Ak.sayamatisuutra. 13. Ratnadaasa, Gu.naparyantastotra, stanza 33. 14. Naagaarjuna, Catu.hstava,I.9. p. 367 Thus, the purport of emptiness is the function of emptiness, not its essence; for it has no essence.(15) Similarly, the purport of compassion is the function of compassion. Emptiness and compassion exist both for the sake of enlightenment. But, what is this enlightenment (bodhi)? It is nothing less than the very practice of perfection (paaramitaa) , particularly that of altruism. "For giving," says the Ratnamegha, "is the enlightenment of the bodhisattva."(16) With the culmination of the bodhisattva's path, he does not abandon other living beings, by the power of his vow he remains in sa^msaara. In the words of the first Bhaavanaakrama: ... although he is in possession of the knowledge that all dharmas have no own-existence, concern for all beings has not ceased, insofar as "[bodhisattvas] abide with the defects of sa^msaara, unsoiled by sa^msaara. But, how can there be this effortless serenity? The cause is explained as follows: "He perceives through the nonrepresentation of a supreme selfless knowledge." Because that knowledge of the nondualists which is characterized by nonduality, and which is considered by them to be the supreme, from the point of view of the ultimate goal, even that knowledge, the yogin perceives as selfless, lacking ownexistence, by means of the knowledge of the nonrepresentation of a nonduality. Therefore, since there is nothing else to be seen, it is effortless; since there is no imagination left, it is serenity.(17) Thus, there is a saintly illusion that the true bodhisattva must overcome as much as he must conquer worldly illusion. The illusion of the ultimate goal deceives through the magic trickery of virtue and knowledge (pu.nyaj~naanaa- sambhaaramaayaa) ; its antidote is the conjunction of wisdom and means (praj~nopaaya-yuganaddha), and this union is effected through true detachment; even in the vision of the ultimate goal, bodhisattvas do not find a foothold, for they do not reject the truth of covering (sa^mv.rti). Not cutting away convention, preceded by great compassion, free of perverted views, they dedicate themselves to the fulfillment of the welfare of living beings. If it would happen that they abide in this supramundane wisdom [only], then there would be no dedication to the means [to save others]. But, because the bodhisattva is free from perverted views when he dedicates --------------------------- 15. In this connection one should consider the celebrated passage in the MK., often quoted in favor of the Pure Land doctrine: "To this we reply that you do not understand the purpose of emptiness, nor emptiness itself, nor the meaning of emptiness, thus you defeat yourselves." (XXIV.7) See Tsutsumu Yamaguchi, Daijoo to shite no joda, Tokyo, 1966, pp. 37-39 (first pointed out to me by my friend, Masamichi Ichigo), where a rather loose, but classical, and, ultimately, correct interpretation of this stanza is given. Yamaguchi's rendering of `suunyataaprayojana as the "practice of emptiness" may be rather farfetched philologically, but philosophically "the purport of emptiness" must be its practice. Yamaguchi offers a beautiful exposition of the philosophic problem in chap. 2 of his Kuu no sekai (Tokyo, 1970). See also, Yamaguchi's "The Concept of Pure Land in Nagaarjuna's Doctrine," The Eastern Buddhist 1 (1966): 34-47. 16. `Sik.s. 34. 17. Guiseppe Tucci, Minor Buddhist Texts 2 vols. (Rome: ISMEO, 1956), Part II, pp. 217-218. p. 368 [himself] to the practice of [these] means,... there appears the correct wisdom settled in the reality of the ultimate goal [which is present] in [all] things, which turns the practice away from supramundane knowledge.(18) In these passages a characteristically Mahaayaana turn of thought can be perceived, which does not appear as explicitly in `Saantideva. It is the return to the practice of the path, away from the merely speculative interpretation. The bodhisattva ideal points to an awakening to the insufficiencies of the nihilistic concepts of the Abhidharma.(19) Bound by the mythology and the logic of the idea of nonself, the Mahaayaana made use of this very concept, interpreted it as total emptiness in an attempt to recover reality. However, in attempting to return to what they considered the Master's teaching, very seldom were they able to overcome the shortcomings of the metaphysical interpretations of the nairaatmya formula; though it was often understood psychologically or, as in the case of Naagaarjuna, as merely a step in a dialectical process. Thus, the Maadhyamika seeks to restore the psychological concept of radical detachment to the center of the Buddhist path by interpreting the negation of self as the basis for the radical negation of anything graspable, of any hold for the mind.(20) The "metaphysical" speculations of the Maadhyamika may be explained as an endeavor to salvage the ascetic and psychological foundations of Buddhist mysticism in its pristine emphasis on selflessness by going beyond the rigid explications of the Abhidharma. Thus, Buddhist doctrine is not metaphysical doctrine for the Maadhyamika philosopher.(21) What is it then? The immediate purpose of his dialectics is to refute all metaphysical systems, but this is only in order to bring about ------------------------------- 18. Ibid., p. 221. The Tibetan text lacks most of this passage. 19. This tendency finds its culmination in the school of Saaramati, and suutras such as the Mahaaparinirvaa.na of the Mahaayaana, where emptiness and nonself are given up altogether as ultimate truths. 20. Cf. Bcaa. IX.28-35 and Pa~njikaa thereto, also MK. XIII.7-8, XVI.9, and XXV.24. 21. Cf. Pa~njikaa to Bcaa. IX.73 (de la Vallee Poussin's ed.), p. 476: "Nothing arises, nothing ceases, either endowed with a self or not having a self." Also MK. XVIII.6: "The self has been made known by the buddhas, nonself has also been taught by them, that there is neither a self nor a nonself has also been taught by them." While commenting on this and the following stanza, the Prasannapadaa underlines the neutrality of the Middle Way. The commentary to the previous stanzas, however, seems to agree with the position held by de la Vallee Poussin (JA, Sept.-Oct. 1902, no. 20, pp. 241 ff.). The French indologist would identify the rejection of the antinomies in Naagaarjuna with his acceptance of the nonexistence of the self. This would be nothing more than a reduction of Maadhyamika dialectics to the nairaatmya theory. Naagaarjuna's position, however, is that from the fact that no self can be apprehended, follows the nonexistence of the groups of grasping, and from this follows the nonvalidity of the concepts of existence and nonexistence. The intent of the doctrine of total emptiness is clearly seen in such passages as Rat. I.29-30, 35, 38-39, 76, II.3-5, A.s.tasaahasrikaa, pp.277-282, 313-321, 359-361, 441-443. This is very different from the Hinayaama interpretation of the middle way (cf. Ako`s. IX, pp. 469 ff., in Pradhan's ed.). p. 369 a radical transformation of thought.(22) Its ontology has been correctly described as an abolitive ontology: its conception of reality only serves the function of abolishing the grasping at conceptions, the settling down (abhinive`sa) in imaginings and ideologies. After all, in the opinion of `Saantideva the mystic, thought alone is the source of all evil and thought alone should be controlled and corrected (V.6-14). This is the sole aim of the morality of continence. In this very connection, `Saantideva the philosopher has this to say: Once you have adopted the notion of emptiness, the notion of existence disappears, yet later, through exercise in the notion of "nothing exists," the notion of emptiness also disappears. Once you do not conceive of any entities which could be assumed not to exist, how could nonexistence stand before the mind, which then will have no support' And when neither existence nor nonexistence stand before the mind, then the mind is at rest, without an object, because it has nowhere else to go (IX.33-35).(23) The Pa~njikaa explains the meaning of these famous stanzas (`Saantideva is supposed to have levitated beyond the sight of his audience as he recited them)(24) as the rejection of any possibility of clinging to emptiness, clinging to the idea that ultimate truth has an essence (paramaarthasvabhaava), or clinging to it as if it had an essence. Nirvaa.na is the stopping of this clinging. As expressed in the Ratnaavalii: "Nirvaa.na is the destruction of all tampering with being and nonbeing."(25) Consequently, this being the bodhisattva's aim, he should put an end not only to self and the five groups of grasping, but also to emptiness and to selflessness as absolute values.(26) Thus, Maadhyamika "ethics" could be said to rest on the principle of the ultimate analysis of emptiness, especially on the analysis of the emptiness of moral values. In this way it claims to have superseded absolutism and its individual psychological manifestations: self-righteousness, self-complacence, and the rest. This is aptly expressed in the the words of the Abhisamayaala^nkaara: "by means of wisdom there is no station in becoming, by means of mercy there is no standing in quietism."(27) Therefore, the one aim of the application of compassion is the reflexive effect of compassion: the training of the mind in the notion of selflessness. When `Saantideva projects himself into the self of a beggar (VIII.141 ff) he ------------------------ 22 In its moral intent, the meditation on the void is not wholly different from the charnel-ground meditations, which pursue aims similar to those of the Christian meditatio mortis. The meditations on the void, however, pretend to uproot not only passion, but also all intellectual clinging. See passages referred to in note 20 herein. 23. Cf. `Sik.s. 257 and references in note 21 herein. 24. Bu-ston, History of Buddhism, p. 163 of E. Obermiller's translation (Heidelberg, 1931). 25. Rat.I.42. 26. The roots of this radical interpretation of nonself, or, rather, of this attitude of extreme selflessness, can be traced to the Suttanipaata, see Suttanipaata IV.11 (862-877), IV.12 (878-894), and IV.14 (917). 27. Abhisamayaala^nkaara I, stanza 10a: "praj~nayaa na bhave sthaana^m k.rpayaa na `same sthiti.h." p. 370 is not concerned about the beggar's selflessness. If he were concerned with this, then he would be making selflessness into an absolute principle of unlimited application, and clinging would thence arise. As a result of this, egotism would eventually follow, perhaps not as the philosophical concept of a self (aatman), but certainly as the psychological habit of grasping and self-centeredness (mamakaara and aha^mkaara).(28) The Maadhyamika Buddhist contends that the paradox implicit in his position will be a paradox only as long as we insist on clinging to the rather pedestrian view that good can only respond to rational volition. Once we understand, he would claim, that true good is the result of the cessation of all volition, the paradox disappears.(29) The destruction of the notions of subject and agent, which necessarily accompany volition, must be achieved if we seek true goodness, actual goodness. This idea is aptly expressed in the Vajracchedikaa:" ...that which is the Tathaagata's perfection of patience, that really is no perfection. And why? Because, Subhuuti, when the king of Kali^nga cut my flesh from every limb, at that time I had no perception of self, no perception of a being, no perception of a soul, no perception of a person, nor had I any perception or no-perception. And why? If, Subhuuti, at that time I had had a perception of a self, I would have had a perception of ill-will at that time...."(30) ---------------------------- 28. In this connection it is worth mentioning an anecdote from the life of the Sixth Patriarch of Zen: The famed monk Shen-hui asked Master Hui-neng whether he had any perceptions of a self (literally: mind or heart, hsin). The Master replied that he would perceive a self when dealing with his own shortcomings, but he had no notion of a self when dealing with others (section 44, pp. 118-119 of W. T. Chan, trans., The Platform Scripture of the Sixth Patriarch (N.Y.: St. John's Univ. Press, 1963) ) . Conceptually, this story is the exact converse of `Saantideva's exposition of paraatmaparivartana, but in practice they amount to the same thing. In both cases the Buddhist adept seeks to destroy his egotistical thought habits and establish a direct relationship with reality as it occurs. He does not seek to establish an absolute law of metaphysics that may be applied to any circumstance. But in order to obtain this open insight into the ever-changing world and this serenity of selflessness, he makes use of the very conceits which bind him. 29. Too Often Buddhist ethics is considered simply a doctrine of teleology: the aim is nirvaa.na, the means, `siila, samaadhi and praj~naa. Although this might be true of the Hiinayaanistic view of the path, the bodhisattva doctrine, in displacing the goal of extinction away into eternity and reinterpreting the notion of nonself in altruistic terms, transformed Buddhist ethics (cf. Bcaa. III.10 and Pa~njikaa thereon). The distinction between deontology and teleology is based on the notions of self and purpose. The ethics of salvation, as expressed in Buddhist doctrine, tend to destroy both notions: self and purpose. Without self-existence there can be no law of obligation, without purpose, no set goal for human actions. The Buddhist position could be compared to that of the dilige, et quod vis fac of St. Augustine. In Kant's Metaphysik der Sitten (Part II, Introduction, sections iii-v) , he proposes that the highest values of human conduct are, in fact, at the same time deontological and teleological. These ends, which are also duties, are one's own perfection and the happiness of others (p. 385, first ed.). No comparison is here intended with the totality of the systems of Kant or St. Augustine. 30. Vajracchedikaa Praj~naapaaramitaa, ed. and trans. Edward Conze (Rome: ISMEO, 1957), p. 371 Of course there is no room here for ethical indifference, the Buddhist is not merely practicing mental gymnastics for its own sake. His main contention, as has been stated, is that no true goodness exists as long as there is the idea of a self, and as long as there is the idea of goodness. Merit and demerit belong to the sphere of personal transactions, but here there is no perfection as long as egotism of one kind or another is the primary motive: goodness appears only where there is no notion of a person or of a transaction. Much of early Buddhist philosophy could be thought of as a vain attempt at reinterpreting the doctrine of detachment in terms of metaphysical formulas. To this purpose, the concept of nonself--no doubt very old, but lacking a metaphysical denotation in its earliest history--was to fit perfectly. The fundamental question should have been whether any discursive structure could adequately express a doctrine of complete detachment, which often underlined the importance of transcending all forms of speech, of breaking the bonds of conceptualization. But there can be no doubt about the fact that most Buddhists understood the nonself doctrine literally and considered detachment rather as the corollary of nonself, not conversely.(31) The doctrine of emptiness adds a new dimension to the metaphysical understanding of selflessness: absence of self, with regard to the subject, destroys the very root of attachment: the blindness of egotism (aha^mkaara) ; with regard to others, emptiness extirpates the root of love and hatred, of self-righteousness and conceit: the idea of an object that could be possessed (mamakaara). Yet, as soon as compassion is placed on an equal footing with emptiness, this latter concept cannot be understood as a subtle form of metaphysical nihilism. The basis of compassion is the realization of the absurdity of suffering, insofar as it is groundless, but compassion cannot be based on nothingness pure and simple. Moreover, there can be no question of nothingness here, as nothingness is never the object of thought. The nothingness we fear, the Buddhist would argue, is the nothingness that can be conceived in terms of a framework or objective support external to it. Why is this called nothingness? Because the frame of reference is one that is previous to our own thinking, we are not conscious of its all-encompassing presence, for it is our own self. This is the nothingness which begets fear, apathy, and indifference, because the ever-present willing subject despairs when it finds no reference point outside itself.(32) The Mahaayaanists, however, consider equally disastrous the consequences of the conversea; seeing emptiness of self but not of the object. For then nonself is merely an idea that fails to reach to the very ------------------------- sec. 14 e, p. 77 of the translation, from which this is quoted. See also sec. 20 a-b, p. 86, and A.s.tada`sasaahasrikaa, ed. Edward Conze (Rome: ISMEO, 1962), chapter 67, p. 175. 31. One cannot help suspecting that the Maadhyamika dialectitian, for one, is often confused by his own terminological heritage; that the rhetoric he has inherited beclouds his very understanding of the mystical path. 32. Cf, Rat. I.29-60, especially 39-42. p. 372 source of attachment: the construction of ideas (judgments) about things. The dharmas become the new frame of reference for the false idea of nothingness. True emptiness is emptiness without a reference point in the self or outside of it. True emptiness cannot be conceived nor apprehended, what is to be total nongrasping could not possibly be grasped. In fact, in order to be attained it must be empty of emptiness itself.(33) With this conception of "nothingness, " the Mahaayaanist believes, the suppression of all notions of persons or self will not entail the abolition of interpersonal values. For what is false here is not the phenomena of interpersonal relations but the notion of permanent, graspable entities; and only the first is a necessary condition for ethical values. Metaphysically speaking, the problem may be expressed thusly: when an elephant is produced by a magician, no one can deny that there is an elephant, but everybody knows that this elephant was not born, nor will he die, that there is no permanent substance that could be called elephant. Ethically speaking, the implications are discussed by `Saantideva: "There is no sin in killing a phantom, because there is nonexistence of thought in the case of mere phantoms. But, in the case of a phantom endowed with the illusion of thought as we are, sin and virtue obtain" (IX.11).(34) The difference between the simile of the phantom and reality lies in the fact that when we look at a phantom we think "this is only illusion, only I am real"; but, in looking at the world around us we must say: "I am an illusion and this is also an illusion." Thus, in conclusion, of the various possibilities, the Maadhyamika philosopher considers that the following three would evidently invalidate ethical values: (1) If the ego is real (or self-existent), but the external world is not teal (its existence depends on the ego). This is the case of the man killing the phantom--idealism, (2) If the external world is real (self-existent), but the ego is not real (its existence depends on nonpersonal substances). This is the position of Abhidharmic realism. (3) If both the ego and the external world are self-existent. This is the position of the naive realists. On the other hand, he would contend that ethical values are not in conflict with an ontology such as is expounded, of course, by the Maadhyamikas: everything lacks self-existence, including the ego, including the external dharmas. The very concept of real and unreal--which presuppose self-existence --cannot be applied to any phenomenon in an ultimate sense. This last possibility is not merely a sufficient condition for ethics, it also implies ethical ----------------------- 33. At least insofar as we may be allowed to propose a means to represent the unexpressible, perhaps the Maadhyamika philosopher will permit us to say that this emptiness should belong to the realm of mystical psychology, not to metaphysics. 34. Compare Rat. II.9-15. The opposite seems to be expressed in A.s.tasaahasrikaa, P. 441, as it compares the bodhisattva to a man created by magic to whom it does not occur `the magician is near to me, but the audience is far from me'. For a mere illusion cannot have thought to make these distinctions. p. 373 values by necessity, since it destroys the only real obstacle to the exercise of goodness: self-conceit. We must therefore distinguish two dialectic movements in the Maadhyamika theory of value: the first movement is ontological when self-existence (svabhaava) is denied, psychological when absolute goodness is rejected. The second movement is ontological when the validity of causation is affirmed against the contentions of the nihilists, it is psychological when the necessity for perfection is emphasized. One must be very careful not to consider these two movements as two different levels of truth. The sphere of convention or covering (sa.mv.rti) is the realm of conceptualization, the transactional field (vyavahaara); to it belong both dialectic movements of the Maadhyamika. The ultimate goal (paramaartha) is simply the abolition of this sphere at any dialectic level. Existence itself, does not fit any of these conceptual slots that have been called "movements" here. The idea of value belongs to the sphere of concepts, which, the Maadhyamika would add, is not the same as saying that it is relative, as if there were something that is absolute. In this way, as a mere concept, the concept of good is bordering with that of evil and with evil actions themselves, which, after all, are the final outcome of grasping at concepts. But good, as an existential attitude or as existence itself, belongs to what earlier has been called "existence," that is, what is beyond the grasping of conceit and concept. This is metaphysically, emptiness; ontologically, conditioned production (pratiityasamutpaada); and, ethically, the perfection of the threefold purity (triko.tipari`suddhi). The relevance of "existence" to the Maadhyamika Buddhist has often been overlooked because of an exaggerated emphasis on the supposed nihilism of this school. To the Maadhyamika existence is the crucial issue. The fact of relations and responsibilities is accepted without debate.(35) The discovery of existence, as it occurs (yathaabhuuta), and the abandonment of tampering with being and nonbeing is achieved through the path. The paradox is not only that in this way sa.msaara and nirvaa.na are made to be the same, but also that the greatest obstacle to our own good, our own self is overcome. The selflessness thus attained appears as the only basis for ethical action: "If the self is dear to you, do not love yourself. If you want to protect yourself, you should not protect yourself."(36) ----------------------- 35. Cf.Pa~njikaa to Bcaa. IX.2: "ida^m pratyayataamaatram eva avicaaramanoharam astu." 36. Though the very similar lines often found in the Gospels (Matt. 10:39, 16:25, Mark 8:35, Luke 8:24, 17.33, John 12:24-25) must be understood in a theistic context and could be interpreted dualistically (see, for example, the Interpreter's Bible, vol. VII, p. 377), both passages point to similae conceptions of the religious foundations of conduct. proofread by Shie Ming-ju