| |||||||||||||||||||||||
|
ISSN 1076-9005
|
Buddhism | Nussbaum | |
Theory | Declaration of Interdependence |
Capability Approach (Nussbaum 2000, 2001) |
Institutions | Individual-in-society vs. the individual-reaching-out-to-society. |
Compassionate individuals construct institutions that embody what they imagine;
institutions influence the development of compassion in individuals.
In connection with a form of political liberalism going for overlapping consensus. (Nussbaum 2001) |
Grassroot level | Socially Engaged Buddhism |
Cultivating compassion through education and the fostering of the ability to imagine the experience of others. (Poetic Justice, Nussbaum 1995) |
The above description by Nussbaum of the two visions of political community may as well be seen as reflecting the debate between an ethics of justice attributing to every human being, seen as free responsible agents, equal rights, and care ethics, concerned with the interpersonal and dependency.(37) The description reflects the opposing images of self that are used in Western ethics of justice (in terms of rights attributed to a self as a free, autonomous agent) and care ethics (in terms of responsibilities and which sees the self as interdependent and vulnerable). Here, Buddhism can teach us, through the middle way teaching handed down by Nāgārjuna, to work with seemingly opposing traits, and inspire us as we try to bridge dichotomies. Thus we would put forward a self image that is less polarized and encloses traits of autonomy, dependence, vulnerability, and contingency, using an and/and approach, rather than an (exclusive) or/or approach. An extended self would be conceived as a process (i.e. continuously changing), that is fragmented, fleshy, both thinking and feeling and continuously involved in a relation with its surroundings and with others.(38) From Nussbaum's analysis it is clear that she extends the image of the self dominant in Western philosophy. She argues for a self that incorporates aspects like dependency and vulnerability, which the dominant Western theory split off. For Nussbaum, if a person would recognize that the judgment characteristics of compassion are essential for the health of a complete adult rationality, it would provide for the development of a person capable of "mature dependence."(39) Such a person would take up a more narrative attitude in her judgments and use a sympathetic perception like the judicious spectator has in Poetic Justice.(40) She notes that compassion can coexist with respect for agency, for it is only when we see to what extent external goods is involved in the development of agency itself that we have the deepest possible basis for respecting and promoting human freedom.(41)
We could also bridge this way between care and justice ethics, combining what is valuable in both. This would allow us to conceive a system that is more comprehensive, so that we are no longer stuck in the impasse of the debate between care and justice. Attempts have been made to bridge the abyss in some way, but these have not proven to be fruitful. Grace Clement presents a thorough overview of the care vs. justice debate and of its relevant authors. She describes the two views commentators take with respect to the relationship between both sides of the discussion: according to some, the interaction between justice and care results in a convergence into a comprehensive ethic (Manning 1992, Clement 1996), while others argue that the two ethics remain independent orientations on any given situation (Noddings 1984, Ruddick 1995). Authors of the convergence thesis have argued that the ethic of care can be assimilated in the ethic of justice (Manning 1992), or that care is a more basic ethic than justice (Held 1995).
Further research would attempt, using an extended image of self, together with the aspects of compassion (we would lean on both Nussbaum and Buddhism) to develop and substantiate some kind of comprehensive system of ethics. In doing so, we would be able to combine what is valuable care ethics and what is valuable in justice. For this, compassion would serve as a connecting idea between the ethics of justice and the ethics of care, functioning as a sort of liaison, a passageway from one discourse to another. Compassion and the mental ability of empathy, through which we can reconstruct the other's experience in our imagination, can allow us to descend downwards from abstract rights into the contextual, somewhat as if we were "fleshing out" a framework. But also because through compassion one can cast one's own contextual "coat" and try on another, it teaches us about relativity, and this allows us to climb from our own contingencies to some notion of ubiquitous needs that should be provided for all human beings. But using compassion that way without undergirding the theory with an extended self image would not only be inconsistent, it would sustain the illusion that compassion as a way to deal with interdependence is a choice of the free autonomous individual, allowing us to discard our responsibilities in a global context.
Politically, interweaving justice and care this way could facilitate a "think globally, act locally"(42) way of being in the world, but also allow the discourse of rights to do its work in contexts where it is most needed, for instance the position of women in many patriarchal societies. It equally opens up citizens to the multifaceted benefits a contextual approach has to offer, for instance in the context of developing aid.(43)
The difference with social contract doctrines such as Rawls's,(44) is that we would not imagine members of society as only agents, as "fully cooperating members of society over a complete life," as Rawls puts it himself, but that we would take into account that all human beings have periods of profound neediness and dependency. Also, we would make an argument for choosing information and compassion over the combination of self-interest and ignorance, as Rawls does through the use of the veil of ignorance. This strategy would allow for a more dynamic approach to just societies rather than the momentaneous character of contract-models. Compared to communitarian models,(45) which stress common values as being the basis of a community, compassionate societies would add an ability to overcome the contingencies contained in their model's conceptions of the good, which would allow for more openness towards the other.
We would also investigate further how compassion, combined with a communicative rationality,(46) might function in the sphere of globalization. Each time a community is confronted with otherness, compassion is challenged and in combination with a communicative rationality, ideally allows for opening up or stretching boundaries between us and others. Considered that way, it shows its promise for conceiving a peaceful international community that deals with multiculturalism in a receptive, encompassing way.
The bridging process of justice and care would be tethered to a view about basic goods, yielded by Nussbaum's approach with nonrelative virtues,(47) as they are associated to spheres of common human experience. We could ask what division principles compassionate societies would endorse. It seems logical to suggest with Nussbaum, to describe the basic entitlements of a society as a set of capabilities or opportunities for functioning in a number of particularly important spheres of human experience. These do in effect encompass liberal thinking, as the individual is attributed these as an independent agent, but they also explicitly reflect, through the capability of affiliation, Nussbaum's attention to the individual's embedding in society. In our view, this would then yield a dynamic model of international society, which would continuously be evaluating itself with respect to compassion, subjecting itself to a kind of ethical audit based on democratic principles and using communicative rationality.
Apel, Karl-Otto. Selected Essays, Volume II, Ethics and the Theory of Rationality. Ed. Eduardo Mendieta. New York: Humanities Press, 1996.
Barber, Benjamin. Jihad Versus McWorld. New York: Times Books, 1995.
Battersby, Christine. The Phenomenal Woman: Feminist Metaphysics and the Patterns of Identity. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998.
Clark, Candace. Misery and Company: Sympathy in Everyday Life. University of Chicago Press, 1997.
Clement, Grace. Care, Autonomy and Justice: Feminism and the Ethic of Care. Oxford: Westview Press, 1996.
Eppsteiner, Fred. Ed. The Path of Compassion: Writings on Socially Engaged Buddhism. Berkeley: Parallax Press, 1988.
Habermas, Jārgen. The Inclusion of the Other. Studies in Political Theory. MIT Press, 1998.
Harvey, Peter. An Introduction to Buddhist Ethics. Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Held, Virginia. Feminist Morality: Transforming Culture, Society and Politics. University of Chicago Press, 1993.
Keown, Damien. "Are there 'human rights' in Buddhism?" in The Journal of Buddhist Ethics, Volume 2, 1995, p. 3-27.
Levi, Primo. Se questo ā un uomo. Giulio Einaudi editore s.p.a., Torino. Translated: If This Is a Man., 1958.
MacIntyre, Alasdair. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. London: Duckworth, 1981.
Nussbaum, Martha. The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. 1987, Updated 2001.
Nussbaum, Martha and Sen, Amartya, eds. The Quality of Life. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993.
Nussbaum, Martha. Poetic Justice: The Literary Imagination and Public Life. Boston: Beacon Press, 1995.
Nussbaum, Martha. Cultivating Humanity: A Classical Defense of Reform in Liberal Education. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1997.
Nussbaum, Martha. Sex and Social Justice. New York: Oxford University Press, 1999.
Nussbaum, Martha. Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Nussbaum, Martha. Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Peel, Shitoku, A. Syllabus Boeddhisme I, ī. Antwerpen: De Simpele Weg, 1995.
Peel, Shitoku A. Tekstboek voor Boeddhisme. Antwerpen: De Simpele Weg, 1991.
Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge. MA: Harvard University Press, 1971.
Rawls, John. The Law of Peoples with the Idea of Public Reason revisited. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999.
Rousseau, J.-J. . āmile. Trans. A Bloom. New York: Basic Books, 1979
Shiotsu, Toru. "Buddhism and Human Rights: Points of Convergence. How can Buddhism Clarify the Modern View of Human Rights?" in The Journal of Oriental Studies, Vol. 9, 1999.
Vanden Eynde, Ria. "Buddhism and Gestalt." In The Gestalt Journal, Fall 1999, p. 89-100.
Walzer, Michael. Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. Basis Books, 1983.
(1) An overview of the debate can be found in Clement 1996. Return to text.
(2) Battersby 1998. Return to text.
(3) Nussbaum 1986. Return to text.
(4) Nussbaum works with descriptions and analyses of compassion from the theoretical accounts of Aristotle and Rousseau to the sociological data presented in Candace Clark. She concludes that these descriptions remain remarkably constant across place and time. Although she notes that compassion is also central to several Asian cultural traditions, she only hints from time to time to the Buddhist idea of the bodhisattva, focusing on the tradition of Western philosophical debate about emotion in general and about compassion in specific. Return to text.
(5) From The Shambhala Dictionary of Buddhism and Zen, Shambhala, Boston 1991. Return to text.
(6) The Shambhala Dictionary of Buddhism and Zen, Shambhala, Boston 1991. Return to text.
(7) Nussbaum 2001, p. 320-323. Return to text.
(8) Nussbaum 2001, p. 300. Return to text.
(9) See Vanden Eynde 1999. Return to text.
(10) Harvey 2000, p. 36. Return to text.
(11) Nussbaum 2001, p. 342-350. Primo Levi describes dehumanization processes in Se questo ā un uomo (If This Is a Man), 1958. Return to text.
(12) Nussbaum 2001, p. 350. Return to text.
(13) As in the words of The Dalai Lama in The Path of Compassion: Writings on Socially Engaged Buddhism, ed. F. Eppsteiner, Parallax Press, Berkeley, California, 1985. Return to text.
(14) An author focusing on these aspects is Batson. Batson, C.D. The Altruism Question: Towards a Social-Psychological Answer. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1991. Nussbaum 2001 discusses compassion and altruism on p. 335-342. Return to text.
(15) Nussbaum refers to Sober, E. and Wilson, D.S. Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998. According to the findings of these authors, the most likely evolutionary story involves egoistic and altruistic mechanisms. Return to text.
(16) Nussbaum 2001, p. 342. Return to text.
(17) Nussbaum 2001, p. 357. Return to text.
(18) The Shambhala Dictionary of Buddhism and Zen, Shambhala, Boston, 1991. Return to text.
(19) Nussbaum 2001, p. 368. Return to text.
(20) Nussbaum 2001, p. 371-372. Return to text.
(21) Nussbaum 2001, p. 378. Return to text.
(22) Nussbaum 2001, p. 386-392. Return to text.
(23) Nussbaum 2001, p. 401. Return to text.
(24) Nussbaum 2001, p. 403. Return to text.
(25) Nussbaum 2000. Return to text.
(26) "Non Relative Virtues, an Aristotelian Approach," In Nussbaum, Sen 1993. Return to text.
(27) Nussbaum 2001, p. 417-418. Return to text.
(28) Nussbaum 2000, p. 84. Return to text.
(29) Compassion and Capabilities. Committed to Cambridge University Press. Return to text.
(30) Nussbaum 1995, 1997. Return to text.
(31) A discussion about Buddhism, precepts and rights can be found in Keown 1995. Return to text.
(32) Harvey 2000, p. 121-122. Return to text.
(33) The eightfold path. Peel 1995. Return to text.
(34) Shiotsu 1999, p. 10. Return to text.
(35) Examples are described in Eppsteiner 1988. Return to text.
(36) These concerns are formulated by "Think Sangha," a group that combines Buddhist perspective on social suffering (wisdom) with practical efforts to address social suffering by Buddhists (compassion). They can be found on http://www.bfp.org/html/home.html. Return to text.
(37) See Clement, Grace 1996. Return to text.
(38) Battersby 1998. Return to text.
(39)Nussbaum 2001, p. 391. Return to text.
(40) Nussbaum 1995. Return to text.
(41) Nussbaum 2001, p. 383. Return to text.
(42) Barber 1995. Return to text.
(43) Nussbaum 1999, 2000. Return to text.
(44) Rawls 1971, 1999. Return to text.
(45) MacIntyre 1981, Walzer 1983. Return to text.
(46) Habermas 1998 and Apel 1996. Return to text.
(47) Nussbaum, Sen 1993. Return to text.
Return to beginning of article
Index | Back Issues | FAQ | Global Resources | Current Issue | Scholarly Resources | Pali Canon | About the Journal | PDF | Submissions | Subscribe | Online Conferences | Book Reviews | Search