To view the diacritics on this page, you must install the Indic Times font on your machine and have a browser capable of displaying the Unicode (utf-8) character set.
ISSN 1076-9005 Volume 11, 2004
A Review Essay of Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy: Empty Persons
Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy: Empty Persons
By Mark Siderits. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, 2003. 231 pages. Cloth. ISBN 0-7546-3473-6.
Reviewed by Roger Farrington
Birkbeck College
University of London
rwfarrington@talk21.com
This is the work of an analytical philosopher, working within the Western
tradition, on something central to Buddhist doctrine, which is also the subject of
much debate in contemporary Anglophone philosophy. Professor Mark Siderits, of
Illinois State University, describes it as “an essay in fusion philosophy”. By this
he means the bringing to bear of a form of analysis developed within one
philosophical tradition on topics and problems to be found within another. The
new century is likely to see many more instances of this enterprise, which has
an obvious promise. Its dangers are almost as obvious. They lie in a
likely dependence on translation, and in unfamiliarity with the alien
contexts in which arguments are to be found and with their governing
assumptions. There follows a risk of finding and fastening on convergences
of thought which may be striking, but only superficially so. Some such
weakness can, I believe, be seen to mark many earlier offerings of “fusion
philosophy”.
Siderits’ subject is personal identity and, more particularly, the view of the
person put forward by Derek Parfit in Reasons and Persons, published in 1984.
Parfit is concerned with what it is to be a person, and with whether and how we
continue to be the same persons throughout our lives. He argues for a version of
“Reductionism”, on which what we take to be identity is to be understood
as--that is, “reduced to”--the existence of chains of psychological connectedness
and continuity. We may continue to talk of “persons” on grounds of convenience,
but a complete account of reality may be given without employing the
person-notion. It is Siderits’ claim that this line of argument can be strengthened
and clarified by arguments to be found within the Buddhist tradition. The
first half of the book is devoted to a defence of Reductionism of this
kind.
Parfit is aware of the Buddhist parallel to his own thought, and makes a few
ill-ordered references to it. These fall well short of enlisting the Buddhist
tradition in his support, and Siderits’ undertaking is plainly worthwhile, having
indeed a rather wider application than he suggests. The Buddhist-advocate is
likely to be conscious of difficulties of the same order as those facing the
proponent of Parfitian Reductionism. Siderits’ arguments, if they are cogent, may
be open to enlistment towards the resolution of these concerns, in particular to
disposing of the objection that Buddhist orthodoxy both asserts and denies
persistent individuality or personhood. This is an objection likely to be prompted
by any comprehensive account of Buddhist doctrine. The enquirer will register
the stress on continuity implicit in the notions of karma and rebirth and will
understand this to be personal continuity (“At that time Sariputta was
X”). He will register the warning that misconceived action will have
painful consequences. For the warning to count as such, it seems that
he must assume his own continuance. At the same time, he will learn
that he has no soul or other permanent part, and that he is made up of
five skândhas in a state of perpetual flux, and of nothing else. This is
a view of the subject that seems to rule out the very continuity just
emphasized. The problem for morality seems to lie in the doubt cast by this
perplexity.
Parfit is aware of the ethical dimension to his argument. He records finding
his Reductionist conclusion “liberating”, by which he means that it brings about
a loosening of self-concern and some weakening of attachment to existence. These
consequences are of a kind to accord with a main conclusion of an earlier part of
Reasons and Persons, one that considers reasons. This was that it was a deeply
rooted error to suppose that it could never be irrational to act with a view to
one’s own long-term interest. On the contrary, disinterested action might well be
rational. This fits well with Parfit’s later conclusion that our morality should be
more impersonal. All this, in its rather tepid way, will be congenial to the
Buddhist-advocate. What may be less congenial is what Parfit identifies as a
continuing problem. He styles this “the Extreme Claim”, finding it at
least an arguable deduction from Reductionist conclusions. The Claim is
that I have no reason to be more concerned for “my own” distant future
than for that of anyone else. If this is right, it seems at least arguable
that I have no reason to be concerned with the future. There may be an
equality of indifference between myself and others. This has implications
for action and moral choice that may be found disturbing. They will
be seen to be comparable with those to be found within the Buddhist
sphere.
Here is one form of Reductionism, with its difficulties, that Siderits sets
himself to defend. What he argues for is not quite the Buddhist version, nor the
Parfitian, but one that has its own, somewhat intransigent, philosophical
character. He provides--as Parfit does not--a clear statement of what he
takes Reductionism to be, placing it between Non-Reductionism and
Eliminativism. On Reductionist premises, the person is found to be dispensible
by way of being “reducible”--yet to have, for all that, a certain utility. In
contrast, the Non-Reductionist will deny the possibility of any “reduction” of
the person; the Eliminativist will object to its part-perpetuation, on
the grounds on which he would object to the continued recognition of
any entity postulated within, and only within, some discredited theory
within natural science. On this account of things Siderits is also able
to place the Pudgalavāda: it appears between Non-Reductionism and
Reductionism.
I find that what Siderits offers is not quite what he promises. While the
Buddhist scheme of things, and Buddhist arguments, are a steady background
presence, they do not figure as strongly in the defence of Siderits’ version of
Reductionism as we might have expected. Siderits does, however, put
considerable weight on the notion of the Two Truths. If the Sanskrit and Pali
terms designating the Truths may be glossed as “ultimate” and “conventional”,
the elements composing personhood are found to be ultimate and the person
itself to be conventional. How much of a clarification of Reductionism this
amounts to will depend on the view one takes of the Two Truths notion. This is a
topic too large to be considered incidentally, but it can be said that Siderits
has nothing to say about the history of the notion and does not make
sufficiently clear its slow development. The simplest historical account would
bring out its barely embryonic presence in the early texts, its uneven
development through the commentarial texts and the Milindapañha, and its
centrality in the assertions of the Mahāyāna. Such an account seems
necessary as a preface to any consideration of the Two Truths. Reference
to it is needed for the defence of the notion against the sceptic, who
may be supposed to claim that the notion is less a solution to the basic
difficulty in Buddhist doctrine to which I have referred above than a
restatement of that difficulty in fresh terms, providing cover for simultaneous
assertion and denial (“I go on as a discrete individual, even across lives, yet
I am not a discrete individual”). In other words, to put the sceptical
hint at its plainest, the practitioner can accommodate the simultaneous
assertion of incompatibles by way of verbal paltering over the notion of
truth.
Part of the appeal for Siderits of the Two Truths notion may have been the
ready compatibility of the view of “conventional” truth that it supports with his
position on other matters. His view of morality is plainly Consequentialist, while
his understanding of meaning has more than a smack of the version of
Pragmatism associated with William James. Here are the ingredients for what is
certainly a coherent position. What Siderits argues for is a Reductionist
notion of the person spelled out much more fully than it is by Parfit. His
“person” resembles a committee or a “system” rather than an entity; it
is an association of shifting elements, which is nonetheless capable of
self-appraisal and calculated action. The notion of truth and meaning
that goes with this, and to which the quasi-entity, if enlightened to some
degree, may be taken to subscribe, takes all everyday assertion to have
its significance in its value for the practical purposes of survival and
flourishing.
Siderits’ Consequentialism--utilitarian in character--receives explicit
statement in an endnote in which he distinguishes his view of Buddhist ethics
from that of Damien Keown, but it is evident in the main text from
references to “overall maximization of welfare” and to “welfare-maximizing
strategies”. It is most evident in a passage where he defends his position from
criticism by a notional Pudgalavadin. This critic is taken to have suggested
that Siderits” notion of the person cannot admit the concept of moral
desert. He counters with a purely utilitarian account of punishability,
concluding, “I can be judged as culpable only if there is a reasonably
high probability that pain input [punishment] into this causal series will
alter the motivational structure that brought about the original misdeed
obvious riposte to this is that “culpable” does not mean “reformable”,
but to Siderits it plainly does: his position is too clear for us to suspect
inadvertence.
Whatever the merits of the case he makes for a Reductionist view of the
person, Siderits draws on Buddhist resources less than he supposes. He also offers
little that might be applied to the fortification of the specifically Buddhist
Reductionism against obvious attacks. It will be apparent from what has
just been said about his Pragmatism that his view of Buddhist ethics is
less than fully sympathetic. Consequentialist though he is, he has no
time for the central doctrine of karma. He sees the tension between this
doctrine and the Reductionist view of the person, but does not address the
point.
There is room to make one point only about the philosophical cogency of
Siderits’ case. His exposition, and “reduction”, of the person is made in isolation,
unaccompanied by any consideration of the living thing, “the man” as
Locke has it. This seems a damaging omission, as it is hardly deniable
that either the “unreduced” person, or the “system” that succeeds it in
understanding, must be taken to be vitally connected with “the man”--just how
connected being of course the whole question. In so disregarding this
connection, Siderits follows Parfit, and might, perhaps, be inclined to reply
that he was acting defensibly in considering the question on Parfitian
terms. But it is here that Parfit himself has received some trenchant
criticism. This naturally receives no attention There is no consideration of
perhaps the most acute of Parfit's critics, John McDowell, though his essay,
“Reductionism and the First Person”, with its concluding reference to the need
to hold fast to the concept of the “rational animal”, is to be found in the
bibliography.
The second part of the book must be considered more briefly. Siderits
presents what he calls, “the objection that Buddhist anti-realists first developed
against Buddhist Reductionism”. This is commonly the line of criticism
given classic expression by Nagarjuna and found, not without variations,
throughout the Mahayana. Central to it is the claim that not only complex
entities but all entities lack self-being or “intrinsic essence”, as Siderits
has it. This claim has an obvious bearing on the assumption made by
Reductionists, Buddhist or otherwise, that there are “basic” elements to
which complexities such as that caught by the person-notion may be
reduced.
Siderits brings this criticism to bear on the contemporary debates between
realists and anti-realists. He claims that the tradition which produced it has
strengths which contemporary anti-realism often lacks, and considers the
consequences for morality of an anti-realist conclusion, suggesting the outline of
an answer to the basic problem in Buddhist ethics outlined above and to Parfit's
Extreme Claim. He has already advocated “ironic engagement” in winding up his
discussion of Reductionism. This is the stance of both taking as given and also of
“seeing through” the world of experience. He now concludes by relating this
recommendation to an anti-realist standpoint, and by suggesting how the
practitioner might follow it with the disinterestedness and benevolence of a
Bodhisattva.
It would take a book as long as the one under review to deal properly with
the demanding arguments to be found within it. This is a rewarding contribution
to discussion, avoiding the superficiality and confusions that, I have suggested,
often accompany “fusion philosophy”. It caters for its two potential readerships,
of differing basic interests, by way of distinguishing footnotes and endnotes.
It is not easy reading, and cannot claim anything like Parfit’s stylistic
felicity. The proofreading is less than perfect, and once or twice I had
to conclude that something had gone wrong with the text. Apart from
that, the book is well-produced and no more expensive than is to be
expected. It deserves to be read by anyone with the concerns that it
addresses.